7 Reels 77

2021年7月12日
Register here: http://gg.gg/vdl3y
7 Reel Slot Game Symbols Guide Mobile Desktop. Highest Paying Symbol The highest paying symbol in our 7 reel slot is ’The 7 Reel’ symbol in the desktop version of the game, with eyes, mouth, and muscle arms. This symbol also features in the logo for the desktop game. The mobile version of the game has a different symbol, a 7 inside a star symbol. Casino name: 7 Reels Casino. Amount: $80 No Deposit. Bonus type: No Deposit Bonus. Max Cashout: $100. Expires on: 2020-03-31. The bonus may be valid for specific players.Check the bonus terms and conditions for eligibility.
*7 Reels 777
*7 Reels 77 Rod
*7 Reels 77 Rod And Reel
In 2001, the French geologist and prehistorian Jacques Collina-Girard first broached the idea that a submarine elevation (now about 55 m below sea-level) lying about 15 km northwest of Cape Spartel (on the Moroccan coast, 12 km to the west of Tangier) had until about 10000 BC been an island above sea-level and might be identified with Plato’s famous Atlantis.1 In recent years, Collina-Girard has continued to work on his hypothesis, and now he presents a whole book on the subject.
In a brief “prologue” (pp. 7-11) he tells us how he first came across Atlantis in early 2001, discovering to his great astonishment how Plato’s geographical description of the location of Atlantis contained “l’exacte description du détroit de Gibraltar tel qu’il était il y a 9000 ou 10000 ans avant notre ère” (p. 9), but also how the great majority of French classical scholars, led by Pierre Vidal-Naquet, very soon rejected his theory in total, basing this rejection, however, on nothing more but “états d’âme et. . .affirmations dogmatiques” (p. 10).
In his first chapter (pp. 13-39), Collina-Girard then sets out to sketch “what Atlantis is — and what it is not.” Noting that since Plato wrote down his account of Atlantis “400 ans avant notre ère” (p. 13; a rather vague indication — we can do better than that!) thousands of publications have created their own image of Atlantis, he proceeds with a series of demonstrations of what Atlantis indeed is not: no comic strip like the one produced by the Belgian artist Edgar P. Jacob (“L’Énigme de l’Atlantide”) in 1955 (pp. 15-6); no romance like Pierre Benoit’s “L’Atlantide” of 1920 (p. 16); no science fiction novel like the ones written by Jules Verne (“Vingt milles lieux sous les mers”) or François Bordes alias Francis Carsac (“Celui qui vint de la grande eau”; p. 17); no film like the one by Jacques Feyder (“Atlantide”) of 1926, predecessor of many others (pp. 17-8); no enticing subject of what Collina-Girard derisively calls “para-archéologie”, the wild and irresponsible efforts of which he sincerely detests (pp. 18-20), or of “géologie fantastique”, cultivated by the likes of Immanuel Velikovsky (“Worlds in Collision”, 1950) or Otto Muck (pp. 20-22). After evoking the really staggering presence of Atlantis in today’s Internet (p. 23) — with a little excursus on Donovan’s famous song “Atlantis” of 1969 — and even touching on a psychoanalytic perspective (which treats the drowned island as a symbol for the drowned memories of our early childhood, p. 24-26), Collina-Girard then neatly divides the various approaches to Atlantis into two diametrically opposed camps (p. 26): that of the “too enthusiastic”, whom he compares to the all-credulous Don Quijote, and that of the “too sceptical”, whom he equates with the all-too-narrow-minded Sancho Panza. This is a clever move, and it already gives us a hint that Collina-Girard will surely range himself neither with the one nor with the other camp.
After this, Collina-Girard finally gets down to where all the stuff about Atlantis originated in the first place: Plato’s dialogues Timaeus and Critias (pp. 27-33). Here, Collina-Girard’s major weakness soon becomes apparent: his knowledge about Plato, his works and the (historical and cultural) context in which they came into being is a purely derivative one, totally depending on the French translation of the dialogues by Luc Brisson2 and on the somewhat eccentric opinions of Jean-Luc Périllié,3 who apparently believes every word of the story by which, as Plato’s Critias claims, the Atlantis tale came into Critias’ family. A significant number of inaccuracies shows that Collina-Girard treads on rather uncertain ground here. He claims that Plato devotes long sections to “le mode de gouvernement et l’organisation sociale de la cité atlante pervertie” (p. 27); in fact we read next to nothing about the “social organisation” of the metropolis of Atlantis, but only about the ways the Atlantean kings do business with each other and how their once excellent moral constitution declined into reckless pride and arrogance. The time-table depicting “Les grands étapes de la civilisation grecque antique”, which Collina-Girard presents on p. 28, is at first sight highly misleading: next to the indication “400 avant J.-C.” we read “Perte de l’indépendance grecque à la bataille de Chéronée” and “Platon”, and next to “500 avant J.-C.” we find “Thucydide”, “Guerres [sic] du Péloponnèse”, “Hérodote”, “Tragédies”, “Pindare”, “Guerres médiques”; this would all have made more sense if Collina-Girard had written “IVe siècle” and “Ve siècle” instead of “400” and “500”. His description of the first part of the Timaeus — “un débat philosophique lancé par Socrate: il s’agit de s’accorder sur ce que pourrait être le mode de gouvernement de la ?Cité idéale? décrite dans La République” (p. 28) — is again quite misleading, to say the least: The Timaeus begins with a recapitulation of some parts of a previous discussion about an ideal state (which shows some similarities with the ideal city described in the Republic, but is not identical with it4), and then Socrates states that he would very much like to see the citizens of the previously described ideal state involved in warlike action, so that they can really prove their worth. It is this wish that prompts Critias to relate how he came across Athens’ most heroic deed in the past, namely its defeat of the overwhelming forces of Atlantis. Nothing of this can be found in Collina-Girard’s account: he only mentions a “demande” (p. 29) of Socrates, without telling us what that “demande” is. He also gets the name of the fourth participant of the two dialogues consistently wrong, calling him “Herménocrate” instead of Hermocrates. He also states that Plato “affirme à plusieurs reprises que la tradition orale à l’origine de son récit est absolument authentique” (p. 33), but this is wrong on more than one account. First of all, Plato affirms nothing whatsoever in his own name in the Timaeus and Critias, but describes a conversation by four speakers none of whom may prima facie be regarded as a mere mouthpiece of his author. Secondly, there are in the Timaeus just two passages, where the ‘truth’ of the story is stressed: in Tim. 20d Critias insists upon it, but he is certainly not to be regarded as Plato’s primary (or particularly trustworthy) spokesman; in Tim. 26e Socrates seems to agree with Critias’ affirmation, but he has, of course, only Critias’ word for it. Thirdly, nowhere does Critias (or any of the other speakers) breath a single word about an “oral tradition” lying behind the tale: the Egyptian priest refers Solon to old written records in Egyptian temples and even insists that no oral tradition could have survived the numerous global catastrophes between the distant past and the present ( Tim. 23ab).
Quite remarkably — after quoting Tim. 26c-d, where Critias states that he wants to treat the Athenians of that primeval city which defeated Atlantis as if they were the citizens of Socrates’ ideal state — Collina-Girard unambiguously declares that “la métropole idéale, décrite en détail dans le Critias, est totalement imaginaire” (p. 32), but he nevertheless wants to regard Plato’s imaginary story as developed “sur fond de véracité” (ibid.), claiming to follow in this Brisson’s interpretation, who in the introduction to his translation of the Critias toyed with the idea of regarding Plato as the inventor of the “roman historique.”5 Taking his cue from this, Collina-Girard insists that “historical novels are always founded on a truth transformed by imagination” (“les romans historiques sont toujours fondés sur une vérité transformée”) and that to refuse even to consider “la possibilité d’un événement réel au départ du ?roman de l’Atlantide?” is an unacceptably dogmatic stance (p. 33). After having castigated (once more) Vidal-Naquet as the main proponent of this stance, Collina-Girard turns to Périllié’s much more credulous position (see above) and tries to divide the elements of Plato’s Atlantis tale into two categories: on the one hand “des descripteurs qualificatifs, passionellement surinvestis par Platon” — among these Collina-Girard reckons all details pertaining to the virtue of the old Athenians and to the depravity of their Atlantean foes —, on the other hand “des descripteurs neutres d’un cadre géographique et géologique” (p. 34); it may, however, be doubtful whether such a neat division is really feasible. He then outlines “trois catégories d’opinions sur l’Atlantide de Platon” (p. 35), which he finds already prefigured in the account of the Neo-Platonist Proclus. Two of these he has already evoked on p. 26 (see above): the “too credulous” (who take everything in Plato’s tale as historic) and the “too sceptical” (who regard everything as invented by Plato, like Vidal-Naquet); he now adds a third in-between category which he will champion himself: “le mythe de l’Atlantide serait une fiction construite a partir des événements géologiques bien réels” (p. 36). To make this stance seem more plausible, he cites the examples of two ancient writers who (he claims) were regarded as tellers of unbelievable tales in their own time, but whose credibility is now restored: Herodotus and Pytheas (pp. 36-7). Regarding Pytheas this may be true, but as for Herodotus, Collina-Girard obviously knows nothing about the heated discussion raging about this author since Fehling, in 1971, claimed that he had invented more or less all his sources.
Nearing the end of this first important chapter, Collina-Girard cites as predecessors of his ‘moderate’ median position once more Brisson, Périllié and Proclus, whose report of an author called Marcellus he cites with approval, getting, however, (again) a few things a bit wrong: According to Proclus, this Marcellus6 wrote about seven rather large islands in the “Outer Sea”; Collina-Girard places them “à la sortie des colonnes d’Hercule” (p. 38), which is not borne out by Proclus’ quotations.
I have had to examine this substantial first chapter in considerable detail in order to demonstrate Collina-Girard’s conspicuous shortcomings in matters regarding Classical Antiquity. The following chapters can be dealt with more succinctly, as Collina-Girard here is on his own turf presenting matters which may be regarded as largely uncontroversial. Chapter 2 (“Commment reconstituer l’histoire d’un passé lointain?”, pp. 41-64) gives a competent survey of the substantial progress made in geology in the 20th century (discovery of the Middle Atlantic submarine ridge, discovery of the rise and fall of water-levels in the oceans throughout the earth’s history, discovery of the great periods of glaciation, discovery of the movement of tectonic continental plates: pp. 42-6), demonstrating how earlier theories which seemed to make the assumption of a big island like Atlantis in the Atlantic Ocean at least tenable had to be discarded, thus depriving such assumptions of every right to exist Moreover, since the 19th century the discovery of the great age of the earth and of the various means to measure it has brought great advances in long-term chronology (pp. 46-9), and since the 1970s methods have been developed to measure climate changes of the past (pp. 49-51). Additionally, the development of humans in past epochs has been thoroughly investigated since the middle 19th century (pp. 51-4); in this regard Collina-Girard stresses the fact that around 9000 BC the way of life of Paleolithic hunter-gatherers came rather abruptly to an end and gave way to the “Neolithic Revolution” (pp. 53-4).
At this point, Collina-Girard returns to Atlantis (“Relire l’Atlantide avec le regard de la géologie actuelle”, pp. 54-6) and first of all rejects the attempts to connect the famous Santorini explosion in the mid-second millennium BC with the tale of the drowning of Atlantis: “ni le lieu ni la date ne correspondent aux indications de Platon” (p. 55). He then goes on to have a closer look at the last period of glaciation (and its aftermath) in the recent history of the earth with regard to the expansion and migrations of modern humans in Europe and adjacent Africa (“L’Europe sous la glace avant le ‘déluge’”, pp. 56-64). He describes how the process of deglaciation went hand in hand with a considerable rise of oceanic water-levels (125-135 m), flooding many coastal areas where humans had lived before, and he points out that this flooding chronologically occurs more or less at the same time when Plato posits the flooding of Atlantis (p. 64).
In the next chapter (“Où chercher l’Atlantide”, pp. 65-78) he first of all rightly rejects the attempts of the Italian journalist Sergio Frau to move the “Pillars of Hercules” from the Strait of Gibraltar to the Channel of Sicily (between Sicily and Tunisia), underlining the fact that all Classical Greeks known to us (Anaximander, Hecataeus of Miletus, Herodotus) seem to have identified the Pillars with the Strait of Gibraltar (p. 67). He notes that Herodotus already mentions “Atlanteans” in the northwest of Africa (pp. 68-9). To demonstrate the Greeks’ familiarity with the Strait of Gibraltar, he also evokes Herodotus’ description of the famous circumnavigation of Africa by Phoenicians sent out by the Egyptian Pharaoh Necho (pp. 69-71) and the exploratory voyage by the Carthaginian admiral Hanno along the northwestern coast of Africa down to the Gulf of Guinea (p. 71).
Having ascertained the identification of the “Pillars of Hercules” with the Strait of Gibraltar, Collina-Girard then gives geographical and geological details of the Strait (pp. 72-78). The following (fourth) chapter (pp. 79-102) is devoted to the “Histoire du détroit de Gibraltar et de ses archipels engloutis”, starting with an overview of the rise and fall of sea-levels in this region during the last 450,000 years (pp. 80-82). After this, we turn to the islands that existed before the last major rise of the sea-level and that considerably facilitated human travel between the European and the African coasts of the Eastern Atlantic (pp. 83-4). After briefly looking at the still existing Canary Islands, Azores and Madeira, which were not settled before the 1st millennium BC (pp. 85-7), Collina-Girard describes the geographical situation of the Strait of Gibraltar and its surrounding waters during the peak time of the last glacial period around 17,000 BC (pp. 87-90): at this time, there was an island about 15 km northwest of Cape Spartel, which together with six other islands then above sea-level formed a sort of archipelago that (together with ample coastal regions of southwestern Spain and northwestern Morocco that have been submerged since) made the waters west of the Strait of Gibraltar a kind of inland sea extending about 77 km east-west and up to 20 km north-south. Collina-Girard then traces the gradual vanishing of this “little Mediterranean” west of Gibraltar and of its islands over the next 8000 years (pp. 90-93): there were two accelerated periods of submergence around 12,200 BC (“meltwater pulse 1A”, p. 92) and around 9500 BC (“meltwater pulse 1B”, ibid.), and Collina-Girard does not fail to note that the second of these — which leads to the final sinking of “l’île du Cap Spartel” — remarkably coincides with “l’engloutissement de l’île Atlantide: 9600 ans avant J.-C.” (p. 93). One might object, however, that this is not altogether correct: In Tim. 23e and Criti. 108e it is the war between primeval Athens and Atlantis that is situated 9000 years before Solon (and thus about 9600 BC not the sinking of Atlantis, which only happened some time afterwards (and possibly considerably later).7
After describing the change of sea-levels around other coastal areas of the Iberian Peninsula during these times (pp. 93-96), Collina-Girard turns to a phenomenon that is certainly much more promising with regard to the drowning of Atlantis than the altogether very gradual rises of the sea he has traced so far: earthquakes and tsunamis. Evoking the famous earthquake that destroyed Lisbon in 1755 (p. 96), he points out that in fact there were earlier and no less catastrophic seismic events (followed by destructive tsunamis) in this region (pp. 97-8), and one of them (with an impact six times as destructive as the Lisbon one) happened around 10,050 BC. Again Collina-Girard wants to regard this as simultaneous with the sinking of Atlantis reported in Timaeus and Critias (p. 98); he does not seem to be bothered by the fact that this earthquake and tsunami is almost 500 years earlier than the “meltwater pulse 1B” he described on pp. 92-3. The same discrepancy can be observed in his summary (p. 101-2) of the geological rise and fall of the areas around the Strait of Gibraltar: Collina-Girard states (p. 101) that around 9500 BC (= 11,500 B.P.) water levels around the island northwest of Cape Spartel reached -55 m (compared to the present level), submerging some smaller islands in the vicinity; but just a paragraph later he adds that around 10,000 BC (= 12,000 B.P.) — i.e. 500 years earlier! — an earthquake and a tsunami led to the abrupt sinking of the island of Cape Spartel itself by 10 m, which would mean that already then water levels had risen to about -45 m. How these figures are supposed to go together escapes me. Ignoring this discrepancy, Collina-Girard once more insists on the identity of time and place of these events with the sinking of Atlantis referred to in Plato’s dialogues (p. 102).
The next chapter (“Qui vivait dans le détroit de Gibraltar il y a 12000 ans?”, pp. 103-24) is devoted to what Prehistory has up to now found out about the presence of human beings in these areas during these early times. Apparently there lived groups of Late Paleolithic hunter-gatherers along the coasts of modern Morocco and Algeria whose remains have been discovered in a number of caves and who exhibit some common traits that prompted the prehistorian Paul Pallary to invent the denomination “culture ibéromaurusienne” for them in 1909 (p. 104). Describing the finds of two of the caves mentioned in some detail (pp. 105-111), Collina-Girard is, of course, again on the look-out for coincidences with Plato’s Atlantis story: thus he states that it coincides temporally “avec la fin de l’expansion des Ibéromaurusiens: leur culture va disparaître avec le rechauffement climatique qui

https://diarynote.indered.space

コメント

最新の日記 一覧

<<  2025年7月  >>
293012345
6789101112
13141516171819
20212223242526
272829303112

お気に入り日記の更新

テーマ別日記一覧

まだテーマがありません

この日記について

日記内を検索